[spectre] Zizek, The Two Totalitarianisms
Soenke Zehle
soenke.zehle at web.de
Sun Mar 13 13:40:40 CET 2005
LRB | Vol. 27 No. 6 dated 17 March 2005 | Slavoj Zizek
The Two Totalitarianisms
<http://www.lrb.co.uk/v27/n06/print/zize01_.html>
Slavoj Zizek
A small note – not the stuff of headlines, obviously – appeared in the
newspapers on 3 February. In response to a call for the prohibition of
the public display of the swastika and other Nazi symbols, a group of
conservative members of the European Parliament, mostly from
ex-Communist countries, demanded that the same apply to Communist
symbols: not only the hammer and sickle, but even the red star. This
proposal should not be dismissed lightly: it suggests a deep change in
Europe’s ideological identity.
Till now, to put it straightforwardly, Stalinism hasn’t been rejected in
the same way as Nazism. We are fully aware of its monstrous aspects, but
still find Ostalgie acceptable: you can make Goodbye Lenin!, but Goodbye
Hitler! is unthinkable. Why? To take another example: in Germany, many
CDs featuring old East German Revolutionary and Party songs, from
‘Stalin, Freund, Genosse’ to ‘Die Partei hat immer Recht’, are easy to
find. You would have to look rather harder for a collection of Nazi
songs. Even at this anecdotal level, the difference between the Nazi and
Stalinist universes is clear, just as it is when we recall that in the
Stalinist show trials, the accused had publicly to confess his crimes
and give an account of how he came to commit them, whereas the Nazis
would never have required a Jew to confess that he was involved in a
Jewish plot against the German nation. The reason is clear. Stalinism
conceived itself as part of the Enlightenment tradition, according to
which, truth being accessible to any rational man, no matter how
depraved, everyone must be regarded as responsible for his crimes. But
for the Nazis the guilt of the Jews was a fact of their biological
constitution: there was no need to prove they were guilty, since they
were guilty by virtue of being Jews.
In the Stalinist ideological imaginary, universal reason is objectivised
in the guise of the inexorable laws of historical progress, and we are
all its servants, the leader included. A Nazi leader, having delivered a
speech, stood and silently accepted the applause, but under Stalinism,
when the obligatory applause exploded at the end of the leader’s speech,
he stood up and joined in. In Ernst Lubitsch’s To Be or Not to Be,
Hitler responds to the Nazi salute by raising his hand and saying: ‘Heil
myself!’ This is pure humour because it could never have happened in
reality, while Stalin effectively did ‘hail himself’ when he joined
others in the applause. Consider the fact that, on Stalin’s birthday,
prisoners would send him congratulatory telegrams from the darkest
gulags: it isn’t possible to imagine a Jew in Auschwitz sending Hitler
such a telegram. It is a tasteless distinction, but it supports the
contention that under Stalin, the ruling ideology presupposed a space in
which the leader and his subjects could meet as servants of Historical
Reason. Under Stalin, all people were, theoretically, equal.
We do not find in Nazism any equivalent to the dissident Communists who
risked their lives fighting what they perceived as the ‘bureaucratic
deformation’ of socialism in the USSR and its empire: there was no one
in Nazi Germany who advocated ‘Nazism with a human face’. Herein lies
the flaw (and the bias) of all attempts, such as that of the
conservative historian Ernst Nolte, to adopt a neutral position – i.e.
to ask why we don’t apply the same standards to the Communists as we
apply to the Nazis. If Heidegger cannot be pardoned for his flirtation
with Nazism, why can Lukács and Brecht and others be pardoned for their
much longer engagement with Stalinism? This position reduces Nazism to a
reaction to, and repetition of, practices already found in Bolshevism –
terror, concentration camps, the struggle to the death against political
enemies – so that the ‘original sin’ is that of Communism.
In the late 1980s, Nolte was Habermas’s principal opponent in the
so-called Revisionismusstreit, arguing that Nazism should not be
regarded as the incomparable evil of the 20th century. Not only did
Nazism, reprehensible as it was, appear after Communism: it was an
excessive reaction to the Communist threat, and all its horrors were
merely copies of those already perpetrated under Soviet Communism.
Nolte’s idea is that Communism and Nazism share the same totalitarian
form, and the difference between them consists only in the difference
between the empirical agents which fill their respective structural
roles (‘Jews’ instead of ‘class enemy’). The usual liberal reaction to
Nolte is that he relativises Nazism, reducing it to a secondary echo of
the Communist evil. However, even if we leave aside the unhelpful
comparison between Communism – a thwarted attempt at liberation – and
the radical evil of Nazism, we should still concede Nolte’s central
point. Nazism was effectively a reaction to the Communist threat; it did
effectively replace class struggle with the struggle between Aryans and
Jews. What we are dealing with here is displacement in the Freudian
sense of the term (Verschiebung): Nazism displaces class struggle onto
racial struggle and in doing so obfuscates its true nature. What changes
in the passage from Communism to Nazism is a matter of form, and it is
in this that the Nazi ideological mystification resides: the political
struggle is naturalised as racial conflict, the class antagonism
inherent in the social structure reduced to the invasion of a foreign
(Jewish) body which disturbs the harmony of the Aryan community. It is
not, as Nolte claims, that there is in both cases the same formal
antagonistic structure, but that the place of the enemy is filled by a
different element (class, race). Class antagonism, unlike racial
difference and conflict, is absolutely inherent to and constitutive of
the social field; Fascism displaces this essential antagonism.
It’s appropriate, then, to recognise the tragedy of the October
Revolution: both its unique emancipatory potential and the historical
necessity of its Stalinist outcome. We should have the honesty to
acknowledge that the Stalinist purges were in a way more ‘irrational’
than the Fascist violence: its excess is an unmistakable sign that, in
contrast to Fascism, Stalinism was a case of an authentic revolution
perverted. Under Fascism, even in Nazi Germany, it was possible to
survive, to maintain the appearance of a ‘normal’ everyday life, if one
did not involve oneself in any oppositional political activity (and, of
course, if one were not Jewish). Under Stalin in the late 1930s, on the
other hand, nobody was safe: anyone could be unexpectedly denounced,
arrested and shot as a traitor. The irrationality of Nazism was
‘condensed’ in anti-semitism – in its belief in the Jewish plot – while
the irrationality of Stalinism pervaded the entire social body. For that
reason, Nazi police investigators looked for proofs and traces of active
opposition to the regime, whereas Stalin’s investigators were happy to
fabricate evidence, invent plots etc.
We should also admit that we still lack a satisfactory theory of
Stalinism. It is, in this respect, a scandal that the Frankfurt School
failed to produce a systematic and thorough analysis of the phenomenon.
The exceptions are telling: Franz Neumann’s Behemoth (1942), which
suggested that the three great world-systems – New Deal capitalism,
Fascism and Stalinism – tended towards the same bureaucratic, globally
organised, ‘administered’ society; Herbert Marcuse’s Soviet Marxism
(1958), his least passionate book, a strangely neutral analysis of
Soviet ideology with no clear commitments; and, finally, in the 1980s,
the attempts by some Habermasians who, reflecting on the emerging
dissident phenomena, endeavoured to elaborate the notion of civil
society as a site of resistance to the Communist regime – interesting,
but not a global theory of the specificity of Stalinist totalitarianism.
How could a school of Marxist thought that claimed to focus on the
conditions of the failure of the emancipatory project abstain from
analysing the nightmare of ‘actually existing socialism’? And was its
focus on Fascism not a silent admission of the failure to confront the
real trauma?
It is here that one has to make a choice. The ‘pure’ liberal attitude
towards Leftist and Rightist ‘totalitarianism’ – that they are both bad,
based on the intolerance of political and other differences, the
rejection of democratic and humanist values etc – is a priori false. It
is necessary to take sides and proclaim Fascism fundamentally ‘worse’
than Communism. The alternative, the notion that it is even possible to
compare rationally the two totalitarianisms, tends to produce the
conclusion – explicit or implicit – that Fascism was the lesser evil, an
understandable reaction to the Communist threat. When, in September
2003, Silvio Berlusconi provoked a violent outcry with his observation
that Mussolini, unlike Hitler, Stalin or Saddam Hussein, never killed
anyone, the true scandal was that, far from being an expression of
Berlusconi’s idiosyncrasy, his statement was part of an ongoing project
to change the terms of a postwar European identity hitherto based on
anti-Fascist unity. That is the proper context in which to understand
the European conservatives’ call for the prohibition of Communist symbols.
Slavoj Zizek, a psychoanalyst and dialectical materialist philosopher,
is a senior researcher at the University of Ljubljana and international
co-director of the Centre for Humanities at Birkbeck College in London.
More information about the SPECTRE
mailing list